Demanding more than what you want

Demanding more than what you want (DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/psrm.2025.25) was written by Zuheir Desai and Scott A. Tyson in 2025. It was published in Political Science Research and Methods.

The authors consider platforms to be "pledges that pull policy imperfectly in the direction of their proposed platform and away from a status quo." No one expects platforms to become policy directly. There is a dimension of capability attached to candidates which explains how platforms become policy. Furthermore, platforms are relative to the status quo. A platform that is significantly different should be more difficult to realize; a platform to maintain the status quo is trivial.

Past research has considered non-ideological aspects of candidates to be an orthogonal valence issue space. Studies are divided on the effect of valence advantages between candidates; some have found it leads to ideological moderation, others to ideological extremism.

Downs argued that platforms cannot be compared directly; instead reasonable expectations of what policies will be realized should be compared. Platforms are effectively discounted.

The authors iterate on the median voter theorem. There are two candidates and there is a given representative voter whose incentives are examined.

There is a status quo: s in one dimensional real space R.

Each candidate has two inherent fixed attributes: an ideological position (yi for each candidate i and also in R) and a capability (ci in [0,1]). They also have a platform (xi also in R) that is given the status quo and their capability. The realized policy outcome function π is defined as π(xi; ci, s), shorthand as πi. The utility function they maximize is -|yi - πi|.

All individuals have an ideological position in R, but this mdoel cares only about the two candidates and a given voter. For simplicity, the real space is normalized such that the position of that given voter is 0.

Big assumption: candidates' positions are assumed to be symmetric about the given individual: y1 = -y2. The authors more generally argue that the case of a 'moderate' voter (i.e., y1 < 0 < y2) is the only interesting case.

The given voter has two fixed attributes:

  1. The salience of capability is parameterized as α (in [0,1])

    • this is known to candidates
    • This 'salience' is the degree to which they care about capability.
    • The complement (1-α) then is the degree to which they care about ideology.

  2. Residual valence is parameterized as εi.

    • this is not known to candidates, but the authors assume that candidates expect it is uniformly distributed between ±1/ψ

      • Necessarily, ψ > 0.

    • 'Residual valence' is the preference for a candidate independent of both xi and ci

The given voter's utility function, if candidate i wins, is αci - (1-α)|πi| + εi.

The authors derive a unique equilibrium given a few more assumptions, that mostly are in the same direction as above (i.e., only interesting case is when both candidates have a non-zero chance of winning).

It becomes helpful to parameterize the capability gap as γ (defined as |c1 - c2|).

The important conclusions from the model though are:

The authors connect this to ideological polarization.

Reading notes

The authors chose a shorthand notation whereby the leftist candidate has a negative platform (i.e. πL < πR), has a capability advantage (i.e. cL > cR), and therefore is more extreme. This is a strange choice given how easy it is to re-express everything in abstract terms, as seen above.

I also have trouble taking this model seriously when there are so many arbitrary assumptions about the residual valence.


CategoryRicottone